Abstract
Table of Contents
Part I
Part II
Part III
Part IV
Part V
Part VI
Part VII
Part VIII
Part IX
|
Part I: Longevity in Antiquity and
Its Bearing on Chronology
Appendixes
1. The Hebrew of Genesis 6:3
The following
comments are based on the conclusions of Theodore Preston, in
his Notes on the Hebrew Text of Genesis, Cambridge, 1853,
p.45ff. Although this is an early treatment of the passage, modern
translators adopt this interpretation for substantially the reasons
given.
The Hebrew text is as follows: L
The Authorized Version translates
this, ". . . shall not strive with man," but the Revised
Standard Version has "shall not abide in man," a translation
which seems to tie in with the idea that the period of 120 years
mentioned at the close of the verse refers to the age limit thenceforth
appointed for man.
If the verb be construed as identical
in meaning with the Hebrew word , the clause must
be rendered "My spirit shall not always strive in man," or "judge
in man" (dictating authoritatively and determining his moral conduct
as his conscience).
But the verb seems
to have been taken by the Septuagint and by the Targom of Onkelos as equivalent
to, best represented by the Latin
permanebit as used in the Vulgate. With this may be compared the
Septuagint which has:
The Targum of Onkelos has
i.e., "this evil generation shall not always continue
before Me." Some of the Rabbins derived from "a sheath," translating
the clause "my spirit shall not always be enclosed (i.e., contained)
in man."
* * *
pg
1 of 4
2. The
Shorter Value of the Saros
There is some
disagreement regarding the possibility of the saros having
the 18 year value. In his book, A History of Science
(Harvard, 1952, p.120), George Sarton argues that the Babylonians
could not have been able to extract this eighteen year cyclical
period from their observations of the heavens, and bases this
conclusion on the work of Dr. A. Pannekoek. The latter bases
his argument on the fact that the ancient astronomers
could never have achieved sufficient scientific insight to discern
the periodicity of the lunar eclipses which seems to lie behind
the short value for the saros.
The force of his arguments may
be evaluated by the following series of quotations from the original
paper in the Proceedings of the Royal Academy of Amsterdam
(vol.20, 1918), entitled "The Origin of the Saros"
(communicated by Prof. W. De Sitter, Sept. 29, 1918, pp.943-55).
Some personal comments have been added. The reader may judge
for himself whether the arguments against the statement of Suidas
are valid or not. It will be noted that the value is said to
be 223 months, as opposed to the 222 of Suidas. This does not
greatly alter the shorter chronology.
In his original paper in the Proceedings
(p.943) Pannekoek said:
The forecast of eclipses, which
to the uneducated is such a convincing proof of the power and
accuracy of astronomical science, is not the fruit of highly
developed modern theory, but belongs to the oldest products of
human science. Greek writers tell us that the Babylonians were
already able to predict the eclipses by means of a period of
eighteen years, which they called a saros, and which rested on
the fact that 223 synodic lunar periods and 242 draconic revolutions
are practically equal (both 6585.3 days), that after the period
therefore, full and new moon return to the same position relative
to the nodes. . . .
According to the theory of Hugo
Winckler's school, Babylonian astronomy had reached its highest
perfection as early as 2000 to 3000 B.C., and therefore the origin
of the saros lay in such a far off time that there is no possibility
of following the road to its discovery.
But he then
proceeds to show that the Babylonians could not possibly have
had the insight to observe this astronomical measure, because
it required a kind of "scientific" attitude they could
not have had so early. He dismisses any possibility of a 3000
B.C. date, and questions even an 8th or 7th century B.C. date,
at which time the first useful Babylonian observations of lunar
eclipses appear of any value, according to Ptolemy.
He
continued subsequently (p.945):
pg.2
of 4
It would
first be necessary that someone should conceive the idea of compiling
a continuous list of this sort and moreover of looking for a
period in it, only then would he stand before a problem of the
same nature...A super-human genius was necessary for this, capable
of conceiving as it were from nothing, scientific aims and scientific
methods in a world which did not yet know the meaning of science
and of applying them.
Yet Sarton said
they did know these things and in fact claims considerable scientific
ability for them. Moreover, a scientific attitude may be shown
in at least two ways, in the realm of experiment (physics, chemistry,
etc.), and in the realm of observation (astronomy, etc.). They
did remarkably well in the realm of observation, where no experiment
was required or possible i.e., in astronomy.
But Pannekoek concluded (p.945):
If therefore we do not want
to regard the origin of science as a miraculous creation, such
a discovery as that of finding the saros may be conceived
only as a gradual process, as the outcome of many steps each
of which followed naturally and spontaneously from the former
and in which several succeeding generations took part.
This is simply
to insist once more that everything must have a long evolutionary
history. But what about scientific insights -- sudden, illuminating,
entirely free of such evolutionary history? Such insights are
not uncommon.
One cuneiform tablet gives such
a list of eclipses, but although it is late, there is no reason
to assume that it is the only, or the first such list. This tablet
is referred to by Pannekoek (p.946) as ". . . a remarkable
cuneiform text in the British Museum (Sp. 11 71) of which Strassmaer
gave a transcript in 1894." It is a list of lunar eclipses
arranged according to saros periods.
On page 953 he stressed again that
only after such lists of eclipses had accumulated "in the
course of centuries" could their periodical recurrence be
noticed at last. This he regarded therefore as a demonstration
of the fact that the word did not have the shorter value till
very much later.
Thus he concluded (p.955):
This shows at the same time
that the familiar story according to which the Greek Philosopher
Thales predicted a total sun-eclipse in 585 B C, by means of
a knowledge of the saros borrowed from the Babylonians can only
be regarded as a fiction. At that time the saros was still unknown.
. . .
pg.3
of 4
The
argument is in effect based on prejudice and silence, namely:
1. that the Babylonians could not possibly
have been brilliant enough to spot the periodicity;
2. that all such insights must be accounted for by an appeal
to a long evolutionary history marked by
very small steps in the development of scientific data;
3. that tradition (i.e., re Thales in this instance) is quite
worthless as a guide to the past;
4. that we do not have any cuneiform tablets giving lists of
such eclipses, therefore there were no such
earlier lists.
pg.4
of 4
Copyright © 1988 Evelyn White. All rights
reserved
Previous Chapter *
End of Part I * Next Chapter (Part II)
|